The Problems of Philosophy

The Problems of Philosophy

choose 1 from the attached Final Project Argument Options

Paper instructions:
In your written component of the Final Project, you will analyze an argument in relation to a specific issue. Then, you will respond to that argument by providing a counterargument. Please choose one reading or media artifact from the Final Project Argument Options. Be sure to choose an issue in which you are interested and for which you have enough factual evidence to create a strong argument.

Complete the steps below based on your chosen argument:

Step One: Evaluate the Argument Chosen from the Final Project Argument Options (Pick 1)

a.    Identify the issue that is addressed in the argument.
b.    Explain the argument and identify the premises and conclusions.
c.    Evaluate the argument.
o    If the argument has a deductive component, is it valid and sound? Why?
o    If the argument has an inductive component, is it strong or weak? Why?
o    Remember that arguments often contain both inductive and deductive components. Do your best to identify all the arguments that are used to support the position presented in the piece.

Step Two: Create a Counterargument

a.    Create a counterargument to the original argument.
o    Present premises that support your own position while also pointing out the weaknesses inherent in the original argument. Avoid the use of fallacious reasoning and anecdotal evidence.
o    If you are using inductive arguments, make sure that they are strong. If you are using deductive arguments, make sure that they are valid and attempt to provide sound premises.
o    Use factual evidence and/or logical support from at least three scholarly sources to support your argument.
o    This might require you to play “devil’s advocate.” Remember that you do not need to agree with the position for which you argue. You may need to take on an opposing position to your own personal view and argue from that position. Critical thinkers are able to take on opposing perspectives and identify the strongest arguments from those perspectives.

Writing the Final Project
The Final Project:

1.    Must be 1300 words in length, and formatted according to APA style as outlined in the Ashford Writing Center.
2.    Must begin with an introduction that has a succinct thesis statement.
3.    Must address the topic of the project with critical thought.
4.    Must end with a conclusion that reaffirms your thesis.
5.    Must use at least three scholarly sources, including a minimum of three from the Ashford University Library.
6.    Must document all sources in APA 6th edition style, as outlined in the Ashford Writing Center.
7.    Must include a separate reference page/slide that is formatted according to APA style as outlined in the Ashford Writing Center.

PHI 103: Informal Logic
Final Project Argument Options
For your Final Project, you will select one of the arguments below to evaluate. You will also create a counterargument to the argument you choose. Refer to the Final Project instructions in the online classroom for details.
Select the box of the argument of your choice to view the excerpt. Navigate back to the main screen by
selecting “back to main.”
All Animals are Equal
by P. Singer
Wealth of Nations Book I
by A. Smith
The Problems of Philosophy
by B. Russell
On Liberty
By J. S. Mill
Second Treatise of
Government
by J. Locke
Alienated Labor
By K. Marx
Phaedo
By Plato
Applied Eugenics
By P. Popenoe and R.H.
Johnson
In Defense of Traditional
Marriage
By R. Anderson
The Case for Optimal
Pollution
By W. Baxter
The Social Responsibility of
Business
By M. Friedman
All Animals Are Equal
Click here to access this argument: http://spot.colorado.edu/~heathwoo/phil1200,Spr07/singer.pdf
APA Citation:
Singer, P. (1989). All animals are equal. In T. Regan & P. Singer (Eds.) Animal rights and human obligations (pp. 148-162) [Acrobat Reader version]. Retrieved from http://spot.colorado.edu/~heathwoo/phil1200,Spr07/singer.pdf
All Animals Are Equal by P. Singer
Back to
Main
Of the Principle Which Gives Occasion to the Division of Labour
This division of labour, from which so many advantages are derived, is not originally the effect of any
human wisdom, which foresees and intends that general opulence to which it gives occasion. It is the necessary,
though very slow and gradual, consequence of a certain propensity in human nature, which has in view no such
extensive utility; the propensity to truck, barter, and exchange one thing for another.
Whether this propensity be one of those original principles in human nature, of which no further account
can be given, or whether, as seems more probable, it be the necessary consequence of the faculties of reason and
speech, it belongs not to our present subject to inquire. It is common to all men, and to be found in no other race
of animals, which seem to know neither this nor any other species of contracts. Two greyhounds, in running
down the same hare, have sometimes the appearance of acting in some sort of concert. Each turns her towards
his companion, or endeavours to intercept her when his companion turns her towards himself. This, however, is
not  the  effect  of  any  contract,  but  of  the  accidental  concurrence  of  their  passions  in  the  same  object  at  that
particular  time.  Nobody  ever  saw  a  dog  make  a  fair  and  deliberate  exchange  of  one  bone  for  another  with
another dog. Nobody ever saw one animal, by its gestures and natural cries signify to another, this is mine, that
yours;  I  am  willing  to  give  this  for  that.  When  an  animal  wants  to  obtain  something  either  of  a  man,  or  of
another animal, it has no other means of persuasion, but to gain the favour of those whose service it requires. A
puppy fawns upon its dam, and a spaniel endeavours, by a thousand attractions, to engage the attention of its
master who is at dinner, when it wants to be fed by him. Man sometimes uses the same arts with his brethren,
and when he has no other means of engaging them to act according to his inclinations, endeavours by every
servile  and  fawning  attention  to  obtain  their  good  will.  He  has  not  time,  however,  to  do  this  upon  every
occasion.  In  civilized  society  he  stands  at  all  times  in  need  of  the  co-operation  and  assistance  of  great
multitudes, while his whole life is scarce sufficient to gain the friendship of a few persons. In almost every other
race of animals, each individual, when it is grown up to maturity, is entirely independent, and in its natural state
has occasion for the assistance of no other living creature. But man has almost constant occasion for the help of
his brethren, and it is in vain for him to expect it from their benevolence only. He will be more likely to prevail
if he can interest their self-love in his favour, and shew them that it is for their own advantage to do for him
what he requires of them. Whoever offers  to another a bargain of any kind, proposes to do this. Give me that
which  I  want,  and  you  shall  have  this  which  you  want,  is  the  meaning  of  every  such  offer;  and  it  is  in  this
manner that we obtain from one another the far greater part of those good offices which we stand in need of. It
is not from the benevolence of the butcher, the brewer, or the baker that we expect our dinner, but from their
regard to their own interest. We address ourselves, not to their humanity, but to their self -love, and never talk to
From The Wealth of Nations by A. Smith
Back to
Main
them of our own necessities, but of their advantages. Nobody but a beggar chooses to depend chiefly upon the
benevolence of his fellow-citizens. Even a beggar does not depend upon it entirely. The charity of well-disposed
people,  indeed,  supplies  him  with  the  whole  fund  of  his  subsistence.  But  though  this  principle  ultimately
provides him with all the necessaries of life which he has occasion for, it neither does nor can provide him with
them as he has occasion for them. The greater part of his occasion al wants are supplied in the same manner as
those  of  other  people,  by  treaty,  by  barter,  and  by  purchase.  With  the  money  which  one  man  gives  him  he
purchases food. The old clothes which another bestows upon him he exchanges for other clothes which suit him
better, or for lodging, or for food, or for money, with which he can buy either food, clothes, or lodging, as he
has occasion.
As it is by treaty, by barter, and by purchase, that we obtain from one another the greater part of those
mutual good offices which we stand in need of, so it is this same trucking disposition which originally gives
occasion  to  the  division  of  labour.  In  a  tribe  of  hunters  or  shepherds,  a  particular  person  makes  bows  and
arrows, for example, with more readiness and dexterity than any other. He frequently exchanges them for cattle
or for venison, with his companions; and he finds at last that he can, in this manner, get more cattle and venison,
than if he himself went to the field to catch them. From a regard to his own interest, the refore, the making of
bows and arrows grows to be his chief business, and he becomes a sort of armourer. Another excels in making
the frames and covers of their little huts or moveable houses. He is accustomed to be of use in this way to his
neighbours, who reward him in the same manner with cattle and with venison, till at last he finds it his interest
to dedicate himself entirely to this employment, and to become a sort of house-carpenter. In the same manner a
third  becomes  a  smith  or  a  brazier;  a  fourth,  a  tanner  or  dresser  of  hides  or  skins,  the  principal  part  of  the
clothing of savages. And thus the certainty of being able to exchange all that surplus part of the produce of his
own labour, which is over and above his own consumption, for such parts of the produce of other men’s labour
as he may have occasion for, encourages every man to apply himself to a particular occupation, and to cultivate
and bring to perfection whatever talent of genius he may possess for that particular species of business.
The difference of natural talents in different men, is, in reality, much less than we are aware of; and the
very different genius which appears to distinguish men of different professions, when grown up to maturity, is
not upon many occasions so much the cause, as the effect of the division of labour. The difference between the
most dissimilar characters, between a philosopher and a common street porter, for example, seems to arise not
so much from nature, as from habit, custom, and education. When they came in to the world, and for the first six
or eight years of their existence, they were, perhaps, very much alike, and neither their parents nor play-fellows
could  perceive  any  remarkable  difference.  About  that  age,  or  soon  after,  they  come  to  be  employed  in  very
different occupations. The difference of talents comes then to be taken notice of, and widens by degrees, till at
last the vanity of the philosopher is willing to acknowledge scarce any resemblance. But without the disposition
to truck, barter, and exchange, every man must have procured to himself every necessary and conveniency of
life which he wanted. All must have had the same duties to perform, and the same work to do, and there could
have been no such difference of employment as could alone give occasion to any great difference of talents.
As it is this disposition which forms that difference of talents, so remarkable among men of different
professions,  so  it  is  this  same  disposition  which  renders  that  difference  useful.  Many  tribes  of  animals,
acknowledged to be all of the same species, derive from nature a much more remarkable distinction of genius,
than what, antecedent to custom and education, appears to take place among men. By nature a philosopher is
not in genius and disposition half so different from a street porter, as a mastiff is from a grey-hound, or a greyhound from a spaniel, or this last from a shepherd’s dog. Those different tribes of animals, however, though all
of the same species are of scarce any use to one another. The strength of the mastiff is not in the least supported
either by the swiftness of the greyhound, or by the sagacity of the spaniel, or by the docility of the shepherd’s
dog.  The  effects  of  those  different  geniuses  and  talents,  for  want  of  the  power  or  disposition  to  barter  and
exchange,  cannot  be  brought  into  a  common  stock,  and  do  not  in  the  least  contribute  to  the  better
accommodation  and  conveniency  of  the  species.  Each  animal  is  still  obliged  to  support  and  defend  itself,
separately and independently, and derives no sort of advantage from that variety of talents with which nature
has  distinguished  its  fellows.  Among  men,  on  the  contrary,  the  most  dissimilar  geniuses  are  of  use  to  one
another;  the  different  produces  of  their  respective  talents,  by  the  general  disposition  to  truck,  barter,  and
exchange, being brought, as it were, into a common stock, where every man may purchase whatever part of the
produce of other men’s talents he has occasion for.
APA Citation:
Smith, A. (1776). Of the principle which gives occasion to the division of labour. In The
wealth of nations (Book 1). Retrieved from http://www.gutenberg.org/files/3300/3300-h/3300-h.htm#link2HCH0002
On Our Knowledge of Universals
We are all convinced that the sun will rise to-morrow. Why? Is this belief a mere blind outcome of past
experience, or can it be justified as a reasonable belief?
It is obvious that if we are asked why we believe that the sun will rise to-morrow, we shall  naturally
answer ‘Because it always has risen every day’. We have a firm belief that it will rise in the future, because it
has risen in the past. If we are challenged as to why we believe that it will continue to rise as heretofore, we
may appeal to the laws of motion: the earth, we shall say, is a freely rotating body, and such bodies do not cease
to  rotate  unless  something  interferes  from  outside,  and  there  is  nothing  outside  to  interfere  with  the  earth
between now and to-morrow. Of course it might be doubted whether we are quite certain that there is nothing
outside  to  interfere,  but  this  is  not  the  interesting  doubt.  The  interesting  doubt  is  as  to  whether  the  laws  of
motion will remain in operation until to-morrow. If this doubt is raised, we find ourselves in the same position
as when the doubt about the sunrise was first raised.
The only reason for believing that the laws of motion will remain in operation is that they have operated
hitherto,  so  far  as  our  knowledge  of  the  past  enables  us  to  judge.  It  is  true  that  we  have  a  greater  body  of
evidence  from  the  past  in  favour  of  the  laws  of  motion  than  we  have  in  favour  of  the  sunrise,  because  the
sunrise is merely a particular case of fulfilment of the laws of motion, and there are countless other partic ular
cases. But the real question is: Do any number of cases of a law being fulfilled in the past afford evidence that it
will be fulfilled in the future? If not, it becomes plain that we have no ground whatever for expecting the sun to
rise to-morrow, or for expecting the bread we shall eat at our next meal not to poison us, or for any of the other
scarcely conscious expectations that control our daily lives. It is to be observed that all such expectations are
only  probable; thus we  have not to seek for  a  proof that they  must  be fulfilled, but only  for some reason in
favour of the view that they are likely to be fulfilled.
The belief that the sun will rise to-morrow might be falsified if the earth came suddenly into contact
with a large body which destroyed its rotation; but the laws of motion and the law of gravitation would not be
infringed by such an event. The business of science is to find uniformities, such as the laws of motion and the
law of gravitation, to which, so far as our experience extends, t here are no exceptions. In this search science has
been remarkably successful, and it may be conceded that such uniformities have held hitherto. This brings us
From The Problems of Philosophy by B. Russell
Back to
Main
back to the question: Have we any reason, assuming that they have always held in the past, to suppose that they
will hold in the future?
It  must  be  conceded,  to  begin  with,  that  the  fact  that  two  things  have  been  found  often  together  and
never apart does not, by itself, suffice to prove demonstratively that they will be found together in the next case
we examine. The most we can hope is that the oftener things are found together, the more probable it becomes
that  they  will  be  found  together  another  time,  and  that,  if  they  have  been  found  together  often  enough,  the
probability will amount almost  to certainty. It can never quite reach certainty, because we know that in spite of
frequent repetitions there sometimes is a failure at the last, as in the case of the chicken whose neck is wrung.
Thus probability is all we ought to seek.
It might be urged,  as  against the view we are  advocating, that we know all natural phenomena to be
subject to the reign of law, and that sometimes, on the basis of observation, we can see that only one law can
possibly fit the facts of the case. Now to this view there are two  answers. The first is that, even if  some  law
which has no exceptions applies to our case, we can never, in practice, be sure that we have discovered that law
and not one to which there are exceptions. The  second is that the reign  of law would seem to be itself only
probable, and that our belief that it will hold in the future, or in unexamined cases in the past, is itself based
upon the very principle we are examining.
It should be noted that probability is always relative to certain data. In our case, the   data are merely the
known cases of coexistence of A and B. There may be other data, which  might  be taken into account, which
would gravely alter the probability. For example, a man who had seen a great many white swans might argue,
by our principle, that on the data it was probable  that all swans were white, and this might be a perfectly sound
argument. The argument is not disproved by the fact that some swans are black, because a thing may very well
happen in spite of the fact that some data render it improbable. In the case of the swans, a man might know that
colour is a very variable characteristic in many species of animals, and that, therefore, an induction as to colour
is  peculiarly  liable  to  error.  But  this  knowledge  would  be  a  fresh  datum,  by  no  mea ns  proving  that  the
probability relatively to our previous data had been wrongly estimated. The fact, therefore, that things often fail
to fulfil our expectations is no evidence that our expectations will not  probably  be fulfilled in a given case or a
given class of cases. Thus our inductive principle is at any rate not capable of being  disproved  by an appeal to
experience.
The general principles of science, such as the belief in the reign of law, and the belief that  every event
must have a cause, are as completely dependent upon the inductive principle as are the beliefs of daily life All
such general principles are believed because mankind have found innumerable instances of their truth and no
instances  of  their  falsehood.  But  this  affords  no  evidence  for  their  truth  in  the  future,  unless  the  inductive
principle is assumed.
APA Citation:
Russell, B. (1912). On our knowledge of universals. In The problems of philosophy.
Retrieved from http://www.gutenberg.org/files/5827/5827-h/5827-h.htm#link2HCH0012
Applications
Consider, for example, the case of education. Is it not almost a self-evident axiom, that the State should
require and  compel the education, up to a certain standard, of every human being who is born its  citizen? Yet
who is there that is not afraid to recognise and assert this truth? Hardly any one indeed will deny that it is one of
the most sacred duties of the parents (or, as law and usage now stand, the father), after summoning a human
being into the world, to give to that being an education fitting him to perform his part well in life towards others
and towards himself. But while this is unanimously declared to be the father’s duty, scarcely anybody, in this
country, will bear to hear of obliging him to perform it. Instead of his being required to make any exertion or
sacrifice for securing education to the child, it is left to his choice to accept it or not when it is provided gratis!
It still remains unrecognised, that to bring a child into existence without a fair prospect of being able, not only
to  provide  food  for  its  body,  but  instruction  and  training  for  its  mind,  is  a  moral  crime,  both  against  the
unfortunate offspring and against society; and that if the parent does not fulfil this obligation, the State ought to
see it fulfilled, at the charge, as far as possible, of the parent.
Were the duty of enforcing universal education once admitted, there would be an end to the difficulties
about what the State should teach, and how it should teach, which now convert the subject into a mere battlefield for sects and  parties, causing the time and labour which should have been spent in educating, to be wasted
in quarrelling about education.  If the government would make up its mind to  require  for every  child a good
education, it might save itself the trouble of  providing  one.  It might leave to parents  to obtain the education
where  and  how  they  pleased,  and  content  itself  with  helping  to  pay  the  school  fees  of  the  poorer  class  of
children,  and  defraying  the  entire  school  expenses  of  those  who  have  no  one  else  to  pay  for  them.  The
objections which are urged with reason against State education, do not apply to the enforcement of education by
the State, but to the State’s taking upon itself to direct that education; which is a totally different thing. That the
whole  or  any  large  part  of  the  education  of  the  people  should  be  in  State  hands,  I  go  as  far  as  any  one  in
deprecating. All that has been said of the importance of individuality of character, and diversity in opinions and
modes  of  conduct,  involves,  as  of  the  same  unspeakable  importance,  diversity  of  education.  A  general  State
education is a mere contrivance for moulding people to be exactly like one another; and as the mould in which it
casts  them  is  that  which  pleases  the  predominant  power  in  the  government,  whether  this  be  a  monarch,  a
priesthood,  an  aristocracy,  or  the    majority  of  the  existing  generation,  in  proportion  as  it  is  efficient  and
successful,  it  establishes  a  despotism  over  the  mind,  leading  by  natural  tendency  to  one  over  the  body.  An
From On Liberty by J.S. Mill
Back to
Main
education  established  and  controlled  by  the  State,  should  only  exist,  if  it  exist  at  all,  as  one  among  many
competing experiments, carried on for the purpose of example and stimulus, to keep the others up to a certain
standard of excellence. Unless, indeed, when society in general is in so backward a state that it could not or
would  not  provide  for  itself  any  proper  institutions  of  education,  unless  the  government  undertook  the  task;
then, indeed, the government may, as the less of two great evils, take upon itself the business of schools and
universities, as  it may that of joint stock companies, when private enterprise, in a shape fitted for undertaking
great works of industry, does not exist in the country. But in general, if the country contains a sufficient number
of  persons  qualified  to  provide  education  under  government  auspices,  the  same  persons  would  be  able  and
willing  to  give  an  equally  good  education  on  the  voluntary  principle,  under  the  assurance  of  remuneration
afforded  by  a  law  rendering  education  compulsory,  combined  with  State  aid  to  those  unable  to  defray  the
expense.
The  instrument  for  enforcing  the  law  could  be  no  other  than  public  examinations,  extending  to  all
children,  and  beginning  at  an  early  age.  An  age  might  be  fixed  at  which  every  child  must  be  examined,  to
ascertain if he (or she) is able to read. If a child proves unable, the father, unless he has some sufficient ground
of excuse, might be subjected to a moderate fine, to be worked out, if necessary, by his labour, and the child
might be put to school at his expense. Once in every year  the examination should be renewed, with a gradually
extending range of subjects, so as to make the universal acquisition, and what is more, retention, of a certain
minimum  of  general  knowledge,  virtually  compulsory.  Beyond  that  minimum,  there  should  be  voluntary
examinations  on  all  subjects,  at  which  all  who  come  up  to  a  certain  standard  of  proficiency  might  claim  a
certificate.  To  prevent  the  State  from  exercising,  through  these  arrangements,  an  improper  influence  over
opinion,  the  knowledge  required  for  passing  an  examination  (beyond  the  merely  instrumental  parts  of
knowledge, such as languages and their use) should, even in the higher class of examinations, be confined to
facts and positive science exclusively. The examinations on religion, politics, or  other disputed topics, should
not turn on the truth or falsehood of opinions, but on the matter of fact that such and such an opinion is held, on
such grounds, by such authors, or schools, or churches. Under this system, the rising generation would be no
worse off in regard to all disputed truths, than they are at present; they would be brought up either churchmen or
dissenters as they now are, the state merely taking care that they should be instructed churchmen, or instructed
dissenters. There would be nothing to hinder them from being taught religion, if their parents chose, at the same
schools where they were taught other things. All attempts by the state to bias the conclusions of its citizens on
disputed subjects, are evil; but it may very properly offer to ascertain and certify that a person possesses the
knowledge, requisite to make his conclusions, on any given subject, worth attending to. A student of philosophy
would be the better for being able to stand an examination both in Locke and in Kant, whichever of the two he
takes  up  with,  or  even  if  with  neither:  and  there  is  no  reasonable  objection  to  examining  an  atheist  in  the
evidences of Christianity, provided he is not required to profess a belief in them.
APA Citation:
Mill, J.S. (1859). Applications. In On liberty. Retrieved from
http://www.gutenberg.org/files/34901/34901-h/34901-h.htm
Of the State of War
THE state of war is a state of enmity and destruction: and therefore declaring by word or action, not a
passionate and hasty, but a sedate settled design upon another man’s life, puts him in a state of war with him
against whom he has declared such an intention, and so has exposed his life to the other’s power to be taken
away by him, or any one that joins with him in his defence, and espouses his quarrel; it being reasonable and
just, I should have a right to destroy that which threatens me with destruction: for, by the fundamental law of
nature, man being to be preserved as much as possible, when all cannot be preserved, the safety of the innocent
is to be preferred: and one may destroy a man who makes war upon him, or has discovered an enmity to his
being, for the same reason that he may kill a wolf or a lion; because such men are not under the ties of the
commonlaw of reason, have no other rule, but that of force and violence, and so may be treated as beasts of
prey, those dangerous and noxious creatures, that will be sure to destroy him whenever he falls into their power.
And  hence  it  is,  that  he  who  attempts  to  get  another  man  into  his  absolute  power,  does  thereby  put
himself into a state of war with him; it being to be understood as a declaration of a design upon his life: for I
have reason to conclude, that he who would get me into his power without my consent, would use me as he
pleased when he had got me there, and destroy me too when he had a fancy to it; for no body can desire to have
me in his absolute power, unless it be to compel me by force to that which is against the right of my freedom,
i.e. make me a slave. To be free from such force is the only security of my preservation; and reason bids me
look on him, as an enemy to my preservation, who would take away that freedom which is the fence to it; so
that he who makes an attempt to enslave me, thereby puts himself into a state of war with me. He that, in the
state of nature, would take away the freedom that belongs to any one in that state, must  necessarily be supposed
to have a design to take away every thing else, that freedom being the foundation of all the rest; as he that, in
the state of society, would take away the freedom belonging to those of that society or commonwealth, must be
supposed to design to take away from them every thing else, and so be looked on as in a state of war.
This makes it lawful for a man to kill a thief, who has not in the least hurt him, nor declared any design
upon his life, any farther than, by the use of force, so to get him in his power, as to take away his money, or
what he pleases, from him; because using force, where he has no right, to get me into his power, let his pretence
be what it will, I have no reason to suppose, that he, who would take away my liberty, would not, when he had
me in his power, take away every thing else. And therefore it is lawful for me to treat him as one who has put
From Second Treatise of Government by J. Locke
Back to
Main
himself  into  a  state  of  war  with  me,  i.e.  kill  him  if  I  can;  for  to  that  hazard  does  he  justly  expose  himself,
whoever introduces a state of war, and is aggressor in it.
And here we have the plain difference between the state of nature and the state of war, which however
some men have confounded, are as far distant, as a state of peace, good will, mutual assistance and preservation,
and  a  state  of  enmity,  malice,  violence  and  mutual  destruction,  are  one  from  another.  Men  living  together
according to reason, without a common superior on earth, with authority to judge between them, is properly the
state of nature. But force, or a declared design of force, upon the person of another, where there is no common
superior on earth to appeal to for relief, is the state of war: and it is the want of such an appeal gives a man the
right of war even against an aggressor, tho’ he be in society and a fellow subject. Thus a thief, whom I cannot
harm, but by appeal to the law, for having stolen all that I am worth, I may kill, when he sets on me to rob me
but of my horse or coat; because the law, which was made for my preservation, where it cannot interpose to
secure my life from present force, which, if lost, is capable of no reparation, permits me my own defence, and
the right of war, a liberty to kill the aggressor, because the aggressor allows not time to appeal to our common
judge,  nor  the  decision  of  the  law,  for  remedy  in  a  case  where  the  mischief  may  be  irreparable.  Want  of  a
common judge with authority, puts all men in a state of nature: force without right, upon a man’s person, makes
a state of war, both where there is, and is not, a common judge.
But  when  the  actual  force  is  over,  the  state  of  war  ceases  between  those  that  are  in  society,  and  are
equally on both sides subjected to the fair determination of the law; because then there lies open the remedy of
appeal for the past injury, and to prevent future harm: but where no such appeal is, as in the state of nature, for
want of positive laws, and judges with authority to appeal to, the state of war once begun, continues, with a
right to the innocent party to destroy the other whenever he can, until   the aggressor offers peace, and desires
reconciliation on such terms as may  repair any  wrongs he has already  done, and secure the innocent for the
future;  nay,  where  an  appeal  to  the  law,  and  constituted  judges,  lies  open,  but  the  remedy  is  denied  by  a
manifest  perverting  of  justice,  and  a  barefaced  wresting  of  the  laws  to  protect  or  indemnify  the  violence  or
injuries of some men, or party of men, there it is hard to imagine any thing but a state of war: for wherever
violence is used, and injury done, though by hands appointed to administer justice, it is still violence and injury,
however coloured with the name, pretences, or forms of law, the end whereof being to protect and redress the
innocent, by an unbiassed application of it, to all who are under it;   wherever that is not bona fide done, war is
made upon the sufferers, who having no appeal on earth to right them, they are left to the only remedy in such
cases, an appeal to heaven.
To  avoid  this  state  of  war  (wherein  there  is  no  appeal  but  to  heaven,  and  wherein  every  the  least
difference is apt to end, where there is no authority to decide between the contenders) is one great reason of
men’s putting themselves into society, and quitting the state of nature: for where there is an authority, a power
on earth, from which relief can be had by appeal, there the continuance of the state of war is excluded, and the
controversy is decided by that power.
APA Citation:
Locke, J. (1689). Of the state of war. In Second treatise of government. Retrieved from
http://www.gutenberg.org/files/7370/7370-h/7370-h.htm
Alienated Labor
Click here to access this argument:
https://bridgepoint.equella.ecollege.com/curriculum/file/9e75ffb0-15c5-4713-8608-dbd7764cce8d/1/Marx%20-%20Alienated%20Labor.pdf.
Note: The highlighted portions of the argument will be particularly useful for this project.
APA Citation:
Marx, K. (1967). Alienated labor. From L. D. Easton & K. H. Guddat (Eds. & Trans.) Writings of the young Marx on
philosophy and society (pp. 287-301). Retrieved from
https://bridgepoint.equella.ecollege.com/curriculum/file/9e75ffb0-15c5-4713-8608-dbd7764cce8d/1/Marx%20-%20Alienated%20Labor.pdf.(Original work published 1844)
Alienated Labor by K. Marx
Back to
Main
Abbreviated Version of Socrates Final Argument in Phaedo
Socrates: I shall have to go back to those familiar words which are in the mouth of every one, and first of all
assume that there is an absolute beauty and goodness and greatness, and the like; grant me this, and I hope to be
able to show you the nature of the cause, and to prove the immortality of the soul.
Cebes said: You may proceed at once with the proof, for I grant you this.
Well, he said, then I should like to know whether you agree with me in the next step; for I cannot help thinking,
if there be anything beautiful other than absolute beauty should there be such, that it can be beautiful only in as
far as it partakes of absolute beauty–and I should say the same of everything. Do you agree in this notion of the
cause?
Yes, he said, I agree.
He proceeded: I know nothing and can understand nothing of any other of those wise causes which are alleged;
and if a person says to me that the bloom of colour, or form, or any such thing is a source of beauty, I leave all
that, which is only confusing to me, and simply and singly, and perhaps foolishly, hold and am assured in my
own mind that nothing makes a thing beautiful but the presence and participation of beauty in whatever way or
manner obtained; for as to the manner I am uncertain, but I stoutly contend that by beauty all beautiful things
become beautiful. This appears to me to be the safest answer which I can give, either to myself or to another,
and to this I cling, in the persuasion that this principle will never be overthrown, and that to myself or to anyone
who asks the question, I may safely reply, that by beauty beautiful things become beautiful. Do you not agree
with me?
I do.
And that by greatness only great things become great and greater, and by smallness the less become less?
True.

Yet once more let me ask you to consider the question from another point of view, and see whether you agree
with me:–There is a thing which you term heat, and another thing which you term cold?
Certainly.
But are they the same as fire and snow?
Most assuredly not.
Heat is a thing different from fire, and cold is not the same with snow?
Yes.
From Phaedo by Plato
Back to
Main
And yet you will surely admit, that when snow, as was before said, is under the influence of heat, they will not
remain snow and heat; but at the advance of the heat, the snow will either retire or perish?
Very true, he replied.
And the fire too at the advance of the cold will either retire or perish; and when the fire is under the influence of
the cold, they will not remain as before, fire and cold.
That is true, he said.

Then now mark the point at which I am aiming:–not only do essential opposites exclude one another, but also
concrete things, which, although not in themselves opposed, contain opposites; these, I say, likewise reject the
idea which is opposed to that which is contained in them, and when it approaches them they either perish or
withdraw. For example; will not the number three endure annihilation or anything sooner than be converted into
an even number, while remaining three?
Very true, said Cebes.

Tell me, then, what is that of which the inherence will render the body alive?
The soul, he replied.
And is this always the case?
Yes, he said, of course.
Then whatever the soul possesses, to that she comes bearing life?
Yes, certainly.
And is there any opposite to life?
There is, he said.
And what is that?
Death.
Then the soul, as has been acknowledged, will never receive the opposite of what she brings.
Impossible, replied Cebes.
And now, he said, what did we just now call that principle which repels the even?
The odd.
And that principle which repels the musical, or the just?
The unmusical, he said, and the unjust.
And what do we call the principle which does not admit of death?
The immortal, he said.
And does the soul admit of death?
No.
Then the soul is immortal?
Yes, he said.
And may we say that this has been proven?
Yes, abundantly proven, Socrates, he replied.
Supposing that the odd were imperishable, must not three be imperishable?
Of course.
And if that which is cold were imperishable, when the warm principle came attacking the snow, must not the
snow have retired whole and unmelted—for it could never have perished, nor could it have remained and
admitted the heat?
True, he said.
Again, if the uncooling or warm principle were imperishable, the fire when assailed by cold would not have
perished or have been extinguished, but would have gone away unaffected?
Certainly, he said.
And the same may be said of the immortal: if the immortal is also imperishable, the soul when attacked by
death cannot perish; for the preceding argument shows that the soul will not admit of death, or ever be dead, any
more than three or the odd number will admit of the even, or fire or the heat in the fire, of the cold. Yet a person
may say: ‘But although the odd will not become even at the approach of the even, why may not the odd perish
and the even take the place of the odd?’ Now to him who makes this objection, we cannot answer that the odd
principle is imperishable; for this has not been acknowledged, but if this had been acknowledged, there would
have been no difficulty in contending that at the approach of the even the odd principle and the number three
took their departure; and the same argument would have held good of fire and heat and any other thing.
Very true.
And the same may be said of the immortal: if the immortal is also imperishable, then the soul will be
imperishable as well as immortal; but if not, some other proof of her imperishableness will have to be given.
No other proof is needed, he said; for if the immortal, being eternal, is liable to perish, then nothing is
imperishable.
Yes, replied Socrates, and yet all men will agree that God, and the essential form of life, and the immortal in
general, will never perish.
Yes, all men, he said–that is true; and what is more, gods, if I am not mistaken, as well as men.
Seeing then that the immortal is indestructible, must not the soul, if she is immortal, be also imperishable?
Most certainly.
Then when death attacks a man, the mortal portion of him may be supposed to die, but the immortal retires at
the approach of death and is preserved safe and sound?
True.
Then, Cebes, beyond question, the soul is immortal and imperishable, and our souls will truly exist in another
world!
APA Citation:
Plato. (1689). Phaedo. Retrieved from http://fulltextarchive.com/pdfs/Phaedo.pdf
Excerpt from the book Applied Eugenics written in 1918 by P. Popenoe and R. H. Johnson
There are now in the United States some 14,000,000 foreign-born persons, together with other millions
of the sons and daughters of foreigners who although born on American soil have as yet been little assimilated
to Americanism. This great body of aliens,  representing perhaps a fifth of the population, is not a pool to be
absorbed, but a continuous, inflowing stream, which until the outbreak of the Great War was steadily increasing
in volume, and of which the fountain-head is so inexhaustible as to appal the imagination. From the beginning
of the century, the inflow averaged little less than a million a year, and while about one-fifth of this represented
a temporary migration, four-fifths of it meant a permanent addition to the population of the New World.
The character of this stream will inevitably determine to a large extent the future of the American nation. The
direct biological results, in race mixture, are important enough, although not easy to define. The indirect results,
which are probably of no less importance to eugenics, are so hard to follow that some students of the problem
do not even realize their existence.
The ancestors of all white Americans, of course, were immigrants not so very many generations ago.
But the earlier immigration was relatively homogeneous and stringently selected by the dangers of the voyage,
the hardships of life in a new country, and the equality of opportunity where free competition drove the unfit to
the wall. There were few people of eminence in the families that came  to colonize North America, but there was
a high average of sturdy virtues, and a good deal of ability, particularly in the Puritan and Huguenot invasions
and in a part of that of Virginia.
In  the  first  three-quarters  of  the  nineteenth  century,  the  number  of  these  “patriots  and  founders”  was
greatly increased by the arrival of immigrants of similar racial stocks from Ireland, Germany, Scandinavia, and
to a less extent from the other countries of northern and western Europe. These arrivals added strength to t he
United States, particularly as a large part of them settled on farms.
This  stream  of  immigration  gradually  dried  up,  but  was  succeeded  by  a  flood  from  a  new  source,—
southern  and  eastern  Europe.  Italians,  Slavs,  Poles,  Magyars,  East  European  Hebrews,  Finns,  Portuguese,
Greeks, Roumanians and representatives of many other small nationalities began to seek fortunes in America.
The  earlier  immigration  had  been  made  up  largely  of  those  who  sought  escape  from  religious  or  political
tyranny and came to settle permanent homes. The newer immigration was made up, on the whole, of those who
frankly sought wealth. The difference in the reason for coming could not fail to mean a difference in selection
of the immigrants, quite apart from the change in the races.
From Applied Eugenics by P. Popenoe and R.H. Johnson
Back to
Main
Last of all began an immigration of Levantines, of Syrians, Armenians, and other inhabitants of Asiatic
Turkey. Beyond this region lie the great nations of Asia, “oversaturated” with population. So far there has been
little  more  than  the  threat  of  their  overflow,  but  the  threat  is  certain  to  become  a  reality  within  a  few  years
unless prevented by legal restriction.
The  eugenic  results  of  immigration  are  partly  indirect  and  partly  direct.  Direct  results  follow  if  the
newcomers are assimilated,—a word which we shall use rather narrowly to mean that free intermarriage takes
place between them and all parts of the older population. We shall discuss the direct results first, the nature of
which depends largely on whether the newcomers are racially homogeneous with the  population already in the
country.
If  they  are  like,  the  old  and  new  will  blend  without  difficulty.  The  effects  of  the  immigration  then
depend on whether the immigrants are better or worse in average quality than the older residents. If as good or
better, they are valuable additions; if inferior they are biologically a detriment.
But if the new arrivals are different, if they represent a different subspecies of  Homo sapiens, the question is
more serious, for it involves the problem of crossing races which are biologically more or less distinct. Genetics
can throw some light on this problem.
Waiving for the moment all question as to the relative quality of two distinct races, what results are to be
expected from crossing? It (1) gives an increase of vigor which diminishes in later generations and (2) produces
recombination of characters.
The first result may be disregarded, for the various races of man are probably already much mixed, and
too closely related, to give rise to much hybrid vigor in crosses.
The second result will be favorable or unfavorable, depending on the characters which go into the cross; and it
is not possible to predict the result in human matings, because the various racial characters are so ill known. It
is,  therefore,  not  worth  while  here  to  discuss  at  length  genetic  theory.  In  general  it  may  be  said  that  some
valuable characters are likely to disappear, as the result of such crosses, and less desirable ones to take their
place. The great bulk of the population resulting from such racial crosses is likely to be more or less mongrel in
nature. Finally, some individuals will appear who combine the good characters of the two races, without the bad
ones.
The  net  result  will  therefore  probably  be  some  distinct  gain,  but  a  greater  loss.  There  is  danger  that
complex and valuable traits of a race will be broken down in the process of hybridization, and that it will take a
long time to bring them together again. The old view that racial crosses lead fatally to race degeneration is no
longer tenable, but the view recently advanced, that crosses are advantageous, seems equally hasty. W. E. Castle
has cited the Pitcairn Islanders and the Boer-Hottentot mulattoes of South Africa as evidence that wide crosses
are  productive  of  no  evil  results.  These  cases  may  be  admitted  to  show  that  such  a  hybrid  race  may  be
physically healthy, but in respect of mental traits they hardly do more than suggest the conclusion we advanced
in our chapter on the Color Line, that such miscegenation is an advantage to the inferior race and a disadvantage
to the superior one.
On the whole, we believe wide racial crosses should be looked upon with suspicion by eugenists.
The  colonizers  of  North  America  mostly  belonged  to  the  Nordic  race.  The  earlier  immigrants  to  the  United
States,—roughly,  those  who  came  here  before  the  Civil  War,—belonged  mostly  to  the  same  stock,  and
therefore mixed with the early settlers without difficulty. The advantages of this immigration were offset by no
impairment of racial homogeneity.
But  the  more  recent  immigration  belongs  mostly  to  other  races,  principally  the  Mediterranean  and
Alpine.  Even  if  these  immigrants  were  superior  on  the  average  to  the  older  population,  it  is  clear  that  their
assimilation would not be an unmixed blessing, for the evil of crossbreeding would partly offset the advantage
of the addition of valuable new traits. If, on the other hand, the average of the new immigration is inferior in
quality, or in so far as it is inferior in quality, it is evident that it must represent biologically an almost unmixed
evil; it not only brings in new undesirable traits, but injures the desirable ones already here.
APA Citation:
Popenoe, P., & Johnson, R.H. (1918). Applied eugenics. Retrieved from
http://www.gutenberg.org/files/19560/19560-h/19560-h.htm#Page_368
In Defense of Traditional Marriage
Click here to access the argument:  http://www.washingtonpost.com/national/on-faith/in-defense-of-traditionalmarriage/2013/03/20/d19a0c08-915a-11e2-bdea-e32ad90da239_story.html
APA Citation:
Anderson, R. T. (2013, March 20). In defense of traditional marriage. The Washington Post.
Retrieved from http://www.washingtonpost.com/national/on-faith/in-defense-oftraditional-marriage/2013/03/20/d19a0c08-915a-11e2-bdea-e32ad90da239_story.html
In Defense of Traditional Marriage by R. Anderson
Back to
Main
The Case for Optimal Pollution
Click here to access the argument:
http://hettingern.people.cofc.edu/Env_Ethics_Sp_2012/Baxter_Case_for_Optimal_Pollution.pdf
APA Citation:
Baxter, W. (n.d.). The case for optimal pollution. Retrieved from
http://hettingern.people.cofc.edu/Env_Ethics_Sp_2012/Baxter_Case_for_Optimal_Poll
ution.pdf
The Social Responsibility of Business
Click here to access the argument: http://www.colorado.edu/studentgroups/libertarians/issues/friedman-soc-respbusiness.html
APA Citation:
Friedman, M. (1970, September 13). The social responsibility of business is to increase its
profits. The New York Times Magazine. Retrieved from
http://www.colorado.edu/studentgroups/libertarians/issues/friedman-soc-resp-business.html
The Case for Optimal Pollution by W. Baxter
Back to
Main
The Social Responsibility of Business by M. Friedman
Back to
Main

PLACE THIS ORDER OR A SIMILAR ORDER WITH US TODAY AND GET AN AMAZING DISCOUNT 🙂

© 2020 customphdthesis.com. All Rights Reserved. | Disclaimer: for assistance purposes only. These custom papers should be used with proper reference.